ACTIVE AND PASSIVE EUTHANASIA JAMES RACHELS PDF

The distinction between active and passive euthanasia is thought to be crucial for medical ethics. The idea is that it is James Rachels. James Rachels. The late philosopher James Rachels published one of the most salient pieces on the euthanasia (E) debate in the New England Journal. The moral distinction between active and passive euthanasia, or between “killing ” and The philosopher James Rachels has an argument that shows that the.

Author: Moogukasa Meztijora
Country: Brazil
Language: English (Spanish)
Genre: Medical
Published (Last): 6 September 2012
Pages: 334
PDF File Size: 14.97 Mb
ePub File Size: 2.95 Mb
ISBN: 296-6-74865-807-2
Downloads: 51984
Price: Free* [*Free Regsitration Required]
Uploader: Zulkijora

James Rachels on Euthanasia Notes – Applied Ethics

In certain situations, passive euthanasia “letting die” is morally permissible. However, active euthanasia physician-assisted death is never morally permissible. Doctors can withhold treatment in many circumstances, and does nothing wrong if the patient dies, but the doctor must never, ever “kill” the patient.

In situations for which passive euthanasia is permissible under this justification, there are no morally sound reason for prohibiting active euthanasia, and in some cases, active euthanasia is morally preferable to passive euthanasia. Rachels says that he can understand someone who opposes both active and passive euthanasia as immoral practices, but cannot make sense of approving of one and not the other. The basis of the conventional doctrine is the distinction between “killing” and “letting die,” together with the assumption that the difference between killing and letting die must, by itself and apart from further consequences, constitute a genuine moral difference.

  GRATIELA SION PSIHOLOGIA VARSTELOR PDF

Although most actual cases of killing are morally worse than most actual cases of letting die, we are more familiar with cases of killing especially the terrible ones that are reported in the mediabut we are less familiar with the details of letting die.

This gap leads us to believe that killing is always worse.

First argument against the conventional doctrine is that many cases of “letting die” are WORSE for the patient than is killing them. If the patient is going to die either way, why is it morally permissible to dehydrate them to death?

Either way, the patient is dead. But the conventional doctrine often adds a requirement of suffering before dying.

The refusal of treatment to some “defective” newborns, and the subsequent death by dehydration, shows that some cases of letting die are worse than killing. Second argument is the Bathtub Example of Smith and Jones. euthaansia

It demonstrates that some cases of letting die are at least as bad as killing. Therefore, in many cases where it is right to let a patient die, it is also right to practice active euthanasia. Notice that Rachels eeuthanasia not defend active euthanasia killingbecause he never defends the morality of passive euthanasia.

  CNEMIDOPHORUS LEMNISCATUS PDF

His goal is to challenge the distinction. In a case where “letting die” is immoral, killing may also be immoral.

Active and passive euthanasia

If “letting die” is always immoral, then one might have a sound moral reason to object to active euthanasia, too. Return to Course Home Page. Return jwmes Theodore Gracyk’s Home Page.

Author: admin